Search FQXi


If you are aware of an interesting new academic paper (that has been published in a peer-reviewed journal or has appeared on the arXiv), a conference talk (at an official professional scientific meeting), an external blog post (by a professional scientist) or a news item (in the mainstream news media), which you think might make an interesting topic for an FQXi blog post, then please contact us at forums@fqxi.org with a link to the original source and a sentence about why you think that the work is worthy of discussion. Please note that we receive many such suggestions and while we endeavour to respond to them, we may not be able to reply to all suggestions.

Please also note that we do not accept unsolicited posts and we cannot review, or open new threads for, unsolicited articles or papers. Requests to review or post such materials will not be answered. If you have your own novel physics theory or model, which you would like to post for further discussion among then FQXi community, then please add them directly to the "Alternative Models of Reality" thread, or to the "Alternative Models of Cosmology" thread. Thank you.

You may also view a list of all blog entries.

 RSS feed | RSS help
RECENT FORUM POSTS

Steve Dufourny: "Hi John, happy to see you again on FQXi. Regards" in Defining Existence

John Merryman: "What do we mean by "exist?" That something is in some way present? Assuming..." in Defining Existence

Robert McEachern: "Eckard, Shannon's Capacity is dependent on signal Duration, Bandwidth and..." in Dirty Secrets...

Robert McEachern: "Eckard, The output of those hair cells seem to be combined, like filter..." in Dirty Secrets...

Lee Bloomquist: "Causality is associated with time. The problem with time is that in a lot..." in Alternative Models of...

Georgina Woodward: "Hi Kurt, do you mean through space or space-time? Do you mean the..." in Alternative Models of...

Lee Bloomquist: "An alternative model of reality-- 1. Roger Penrose in The Road to Reality..." in Alternative Models of...

sridattadev kancharla: "Dear All, To answer the question what is an observer? we need to first..." in Debating Consciousness...


RECENT ARTICLES
click titles to read articles

Untangling Quantum Causation
Figuring out if A causes B should help to write the rulebook for quantum physics.

In Search of a Quantum Spacetime
Finding the universe's wavefunction could be the key to understanding the emergence of reality.

Collapsing Physics: Q&A with Catalina Oana Curceanu
Tests of a rival to quantum theory, taking place in the belly of the Gran Sasso d'Italia mountain, could reveal how the fuzzy subatomic realm of possibilities comes into sharp macroscopic focus.

Dropping Schrödinger's Cat Into a Black Hole
Combining gravity with the process that transforms the fuzzy uncertainty of the quantum realm into the definite classical world we see around us could lead to a theory of quantum gravity.

Does Quantum Weirdness Arise When Parallel Classical Worlds Repel?
Quantum mechanics could derive from subtle interactions among unseen neighboring universes


FQXi BLOGS
September 25, 2016

New Blog Entries
Bookmark and Share

Defining Existence
By IAN DURHAM • Sep. 15, 2016 @ 19:09 GMT

What exists? On the one hand, this seems like the kind of naval-gazing question that provokes derision and mockery from those more interested in practical matters. I exist, you exist, this blog post exists. It's self-evident, right? Of course one could simply presume that everything they experience is nothing but a dream or illusion and that only they, themselves, actually exist. But solipsism is a useless philosophy when dealing with the IRS, say, or anyone else for that matter. So it may seem to be a silly question to ask.

On the other hand, when one delves into it more than superficially, defining existence turns out to be about as complex as defining consciousness. Putting solipsistic arguments aside, there are some things that quite obviously exist. But then there are grey areas. In my recent blog post on consciousness, I mentioned that there was a good deal of overlap between the nature of consciousness and the nature of existence. Giulio Tononi, as I pointed out, believes that there are gradations to existence that are a result of the causal power of something. I gave the example of a painting that is completed by a painter, but then the painter and painting are immediately engulfed in flames such that no record is left of the painting leaving us wondering if it ever existed in the first place.

At a certain level, it is absurd to think it didn’t exist simply because no record of it was ever made. This is actually just a rehashing of Maxwell’s demon; there is a record of it somewhere in a real universe because the act of painting it increased the entropy of the universe in some manner. A better question (and, truthfully, the real question I have about the painting) is, what became of the information associated with the aesthetic appreciation of that painting?

To put it another way, I can imagine many fanciful things that I know simply cannot exist because they violate the laws of physics: artificial gravitational fields in relatively small, non-rotating spacecraft, spacecraft that make sound in empty space, etc. While they may not be physically realizable, they nevertheless exist in my imagination which, as part of my mind, which very clearly exists. (If you read the article on consciousness, you may recall that this was Tononi’s starting assumption about consciousness.)

In philosophical circles, this is known as ontological commitment and, as the name suggests, refers to a relation between a language and something that is proposed to be “extant” by that language, i.e. something that language says exists. It is generally understood that the “thing” that is proposed to exist does not necessarily have to be physical. One of the earliest and most influential formulations of ontological commitment was given by the philosopher W.V. Quine. What is interesting is that it centers around what can be stated in a formal language. In other words, it would seem to rule out the possibility of the existence of things that are “unspeakable,” i.e. not representable in a formal manner. This is, of course, closely (though not perfectly) aligned with Heidegger’s famous question, ‘What is a thing?’

In recent decades, physicists have even begun to consider the issues of existence and “thingness.” Chris Isham and Andreas Döring, for example, have even ventured so far as to discuss the latter directly in their work on topos theory in physics, something most physicists might be tempted to avoid, at least explicitly. So it is that FQXi convened an entire panel at this year’s conference devoted to discussing the concept of existence.

While Tononi was not actually on the panel himself, he did, as I mentioned, address the issue when he discussed consciousness, equating levels of existence with degrees of causal power: maximal existence is possessed by things with maximal causal power. Though the concept of gradations of existence is missing, Rafael Bousso’s theory of existence could be viewed as philosophically kin to Tononi’s. Bousso makes the claim that the only thing that exists is a particular causal “patch” in spacetime (this is somewhat similar to the concept of a causal “diamond”). It is his view that everything that we can measure is in a particular causal patch and it is meaningless to consider anything else. It might be tempting to think that Bousso’s approach is just a restatement of the hard-line operationalist view that would deny the existence of the moon if no one is looking at it, but I think that would be a mischaracterization. What he is really saying is that it is meaningless to talk about the existence of things that we have no hope of ever measuring. For example, he emphasized that this rules out the existence of a typical multiverse since it isn’t contained within our causal diamond (no word on what his theory might say about Wiseman’s many-interacting worlds hypothesis). The causal patch does contain many possible histories which, I suppose, might make it compatible with some consistent history theories of quantum mechanics. But the causal patch, which appears to be Bousso’s only bound on measurability, is fairly limiting. For example, it conveniently does not rule out the non-measurable aspects of string theory (of which he is a proponent). The fact remains that not all limitations on measurability are necessarily due to the dynamics of space and time.

Some of the questions I have already raised are indicative of the types of problems that the concept of a causal patch does not address. For example, Jenann Ismael asked how we can meaningfully talk about evolving interactions between the mind and the world if the mind is in the world? The more general formulation of this question might be to ask how we can meaningfully talk about interactions between a sub-system with a larger system of which it is a part. But then, as Steve Giddings pointed out, how do we properly define a sub-system?

When polled on the concept of existence, the panel offered a wide array of views, from Carlo Rovelli’s musings about the “existence” of Hamlet, to Laura Mersini-Houghton’s assertion that existence requires an observer. Ismael explicitly mentioned Quine by name, though said her views are a somewhat modified version of his arguments about ontological commitment. Bousso took a slightly different tack when pressed on the topic and said that, ultimately, what matters are the fundamental, base axioms from which everything else can be derived. In my notes, I wrote “I’m surprised to find myself agreeing with Rafael” on this point. But in hindsight I’m not sure why I wrote that since every attempt to axiomatically derive physics has, to date, failed. I wrote my PhD thesis on one such failed attempt (Eddington’s). So I suppose I will fall back on Tononi’s position: I know I exist. Perhaps the rest of you can be derived, but perhaps not.
78 comments | view comments


Science Funding in an Evolving Economy
By IAN DURHAM • Sep. 5, 2016 @ 20:53 GMT

While it isn’t the sexiest topic for a blog post, this year’s FQXi conference did include a panel discussion on science funding that raised a number of salient points worth discussing. I will slightly abuse this space and pontificate a bit.

The panel included physicist Andrew Briggs (who, at one point, mistook me for Çaslav Brikner) representing the Templeton World Charity Foundation, Ashley Zauderer from the John Templeton Foundation, Sarah Hreha from the Gruber Foundation, and Federico Faggin from the Federico and Elvia Faggin Foundation. Whatever one may think of these organizations—and they are not free from criticism—they have nevertheless funded a good deal of excellent pure scientific research that would not otherwise have been funded.

And there’s the rub: there is precious little funding for foundational research these days. As governments continue to cut back on non-military discretionary spending, researchers have no choice but to turn to private funding that, due to its very nature as private, will never be completely free from criticism concerning its motivation. The fact is, government funding for fundamental research has traditionally been blind to the philosophical motivations of research—good research stands on its own and should be relatively self-evident via its methodologies. Somewhat ironically, many of those who do criticize government as pushing a particular agenda with its funding have actually driven it to do just that by increasing the emphasis on and importance of practical research, i.e. research that leads to applications, particularly those with short-term economic impact. In other words, meddlesome politicians have increasingly been attempting to ensure that government research funding does push an agenda—theirs (the politicians’).

This, of course, is terrible for fundamental science. I won’t spend time explaining the importance of fundamental science here as I will assume that most readers understand this importance (nevertheless, see here and here for example). What I will say is that the increasing reliance on private funding is leading to more fractured research. What do I mean by that?

Critics of Templeton and similar organizations assume that these groups pressure researchers to fit their findings into the pre-existing ideologies espoused by the organizations. So, for example, they could assume that the Templeton organizations might try to prevent the publication of Templeton-funded research results that directly contradict what the critics might see as Templeton-supported philosophies such as religion and free enterprise. Within the larger Templeton umbrella, there seems to be little evidence that this takes place. Of course, the same can’t be said of all such organizations. Indeed, there are plenty that do push various agendas and that routinely attempt to silence dissenting opinions. But for every one of these types of foundations there is one that puts no pressure on its researchers.

The greater problem, in my mind, is the increasing specialization of funding areas. So while many (perhaps most) such private funding organizations may not try to directly influence the outcomes of the research they sponsor, they do influence what type of research gets funded in the first place by focusing on particular areas. This is what I mean by “more fractured research.” Under the traditional model, government funding would broadly cover the basic sciences and foundational researchers could often fairly easily justify their research within such a broad call.

This post-World War II model of government agencies as quasi-independent and free from political pressures is a kind of “live-and-let-live” ideal in which the freedom of the researcher to explore (which is the essence of science) is fostered by not limiting the ideas that seed the research in the first place. But with an increasing reliance on private funding, there comes an increasing focus on the interests of the funders themselves. I want to emphasize that there is nothing inherently wrong with that. Foundations are free to spend their money as they wish and, as I mentioned above, they have funded some very important work. The problem is that it creates gaps in funding.

If history has taught us anything it’s that we are terrible at predicting how discoveries in one area may lead to advancements in a seemingly unrelated area. Who, a century ago, would have—indeed could have—predicted that a theory as esoteric as relativity would become an indispensable foundation of modern life (via the ubiquity of GPS-driven technologies)? Luckily unlikely connections between fundamental research and later technological advances were at least understood to exist, even by private corporations, many of which used to have phenomenal support for foundational research. Westinghouse, GE, Bell Labs and IBM come immediately to mind as examples. But an increasing emphasis on short-term profit margins has all but killed off fundamental corporate research.

Of course, there’s another problem that is increasingly exacerbated by this new funding paradigm. Private foundations such as the Templeton organizations, the Gruber Foundation, and the Faggin Foundation simply do not have the resources of governments or large corporations. As such, they are limited in their ability to support anything other than bold new ideas. Scientific results must be reproducible but, as Matt Leifer pointed out in the Q&A session after the initial panel discussion, there is very little funding for projects aimed at reproducing existing research results, particularly in physics. Independent verifiability is a cornerstone of science. As an example, consider Joe Weber’s claim in 1968 that he had detected gravitational waves in his lab at the University of Maryland. None of his results could ever be reproduced despite several attempts. While this lead to an eventual consensus that Weber had not, in fact, observed gravitational waves, it also helped spur the development of LIGO which recently did detect gravitational waves (and, at the press conference announcing the results, Kip Thorne was quick to credit Weber with really starting the field). What if no one had ever really questioned Weber’s results or been able to adequately test them? What if everyone simply moved on? It’s difficult to say if the world would have been a different place, but it is certainly not clear that LIGO would have ever been built and the broader applications of the technologies developed for it have yet to be fully realized. Certainly, verification of existing results is not sexy work. But it is important work that gets at the heart of what science is: the embodiment of skepticism.

Where does all of that leave us? Eric Weinstein (also during the Q&A session), in what may have been the most impassioned argument of the conference, entreated scientists to stop “asking for money” and instead demand some kind of royalty payment for creating the backbone upon which modern society itself is founded. Stop for a moment and think about the ubiquity of the worldwide web. Think about how it has so radically changed society and particularly commerce. Think about the trillions of dollars in wealth it produces. Now think about Tim Berners-Lee who created it as a collaboration tool for physicists working at CERN. Tim doesn’t get a penny of that wealth and neither does CERN. Certainly, they may receive some indirect benefits, but there is little appreciation (let alone knowledge) among the general populace of the origins of the web and even less desire to, perhaps, repay some of that.

Of course, Eric’s entreaty, though passionate, would be extremely hard (if not impossible) to implement on a practical level and I’m sure Eric knows this. The broader point that he was making is that the dialogue needs to change. Science needs to stand up for itself, not just on social media and in the press, but also in how it deals with those who control the vast majority of the money that lubricates the economy.

Through his foundation, Federico Faggin funds research in areas that he is passionate about. This is a good thing and we need more funders with Federico’s passion. But we also need to recognize the bigger picture regarding science’s place in the world. This includes not losing site of two of science’s greatest traits: its inherent skepticism and its gestation in the free exchange of creative ideas. I don’t have easy solutions to any of the issues raised here and neither did any of the panelists. Sometimes it is necessary to simply frame the question. I don’t know if that was the intent behind the creation of this panel and I hesitate to say that they were successful in that regard. But they did get the dialogue started. It’s our job to keep it going.
60 comments | view comments


Debating Consciousness and its Measurability
By IAN DURHAM • Sep. 1, 2016 @ 01:29 GMT

One of the many highlights of the recent FQXi conference on the Physics of the Observer was the session on consciousness. Consciousness is quite possibly the most enigmatic aspect of human existence. It is at the core of who we are as individuals (and, some argue, as a species) and yet we don’t really know quite what it is, let alone whether or not it has a physical basis.

This fall I am teaching a course on the nature of time (based partly on the 2011 FQXi conference in Bergen and Copenhagen) and early on I introduce the notion of a system. For the purposes of the class, I begin very simply: a system is anything that has measurable properties or characteristics. Properties and characteristics are used to help distinguish two systems from one another or one system in a certain state from that same system in another state (where a state is any configuration of properties and characteristics). For the moment I’ll just say that they are anything that can be measured for the purposes of distinguishing states. I will also refrain from defining the concept of measurement since that could be an entire blog post unto itself.

At any rate, this raises the important question: is consciousness a system? The human body is a system; an automobile is a system; the galaxy is a system. Even language is a system which means systems can be abstract concepts as long as they have measurable properties and characteristics. Finding measurable properties and characteristics of consciousness is one of the goals of Giulio Tononi who, more than a decade ago, first introduced Integrated Information Theory (IIT) as a means of tackling these deep problems of consciousness.

I first met Tononi at the 2014 FQXi conference in Vieques which featured several terrific talks on IIT (and consciousness in general) from the likes of Tononi, Larissa Albantakis, Christoph Koch, and Chris Adami. One of the scheduled conference excursions was a kayak outing on a bioluminescent bay. The road out to the kayak launch was bone-jarringly rough (and was not helped by our guide’s penchant for speed and the old van’s completely useful shocks and struts). By the time we arrived I was on the verge of losing what little food I had eaten that day. Tononi drew the short straw and ended up as my kayaking companion. Ever gracious, he did much of the paddling and allowed me some time to recoup on the relatively still waters of the bay. We had a wide-ranging conversation about consciousness and, in particular, some of the disorders he had encountered as a psychiatrist over the years. It was a singularly memorable experience.

David Chalmers (who was also at the conference this year) has argued that any attempt to define consciousness in purely physical terms will eventually run into the so-called hard problem which is the problem of explaining how and why we have phenomenon-based experiences, i.e. how sensations, for example, can acquire properties such as taste. IIT, by contrast, begins simply by assuming consciousness exists, i.e. it takes it as an axiomatic truth. Questioning its existence isn’t going to get us anywhere. In other words, I could assume that my entire life is nothing but a dream, but that won’t stop the IRS from trying to collect my taxes every year. So IIT takes consciousness as being self-evident.

In truth this is how most of science works. We have to start somewhere when developing theories to explain the world and so we create hypotheses, propose axioms, and develop propositions which are then tested and analyzed. We may find that some are correct and we may find that some are not correct. But, again, we have to start somewhere.

Tononi starts with experience. He thinks of consciousness as having an experience. That’s what defines it. As he noted in his talk at this year’s conference, you can’t “squeeze” consciousness out of the brain. In this sense, his approach would seem to circumvent Chalmers’ argument that purely physical definitions will ultimately lead to the hard problem by starting with an axiom rather than a physically measurable phenomenon (as a note, Chalmers appears to be personally agnostic concerning IIT).

Of course any discussion of consciousness is bound to have a strong overlap with any discussion about existence, i.e. “what exists.” Tononi seems to think there are gradations to the concept of existence. In other words, existence isn’t binary. Existence is based on causal power. Anything with maximal causal power definitively exists. Consider the following example which is one I routinely have used when thinking about the nature of information. A painter locks himself (or herself) in a room and paints an absolute masterpiece. Just as the painting is finished, a fire engulfs the building, burning it to the ground, taking the painter and the painting with it. Did the painting exist?

I originally came up with this scenario in order to ask about the nature of the information contained in the painting and, in particular, in the aesthetic appreciation of the painting. The painting itself adds information to the world and burning it simply rearranges that information. But the aesthetic appreciation of that painting also adds information to the world. What happens to that information when the painting is burned if it (the information) is not conveyed to anyone else?

From the standpoint of IIT, this is akin to asking if the painting ever existed in the first place. As Masafumi Oizumi pointed out in his talk, IIT basically says that it is necessary (though not sufficient) for a system to produce information in order to produce consciousness. All of the raw materials of the painting were already in the building when it burned. Creating the painting had no lasting effect; it had no causal power. By the standards of IIT it never existed. As Tononi pointed out, functionally equivalent systems are not necessarily phenomenally equivalent systems and vice-versa. If we were to consider two equivalent rooms in the burned building, both with the same art supplies and each containing an artist, but assume that only one of the artists painted a masterpiece before the building burned to the ground, the two rooms are phenomenally equivalent in the record they left in the world and yet, since the artists each took different actions prior to the fire, the two rooms are not functionally equivalent.

At any rate, Tononi says that if consciousness does exist then its existence must be based on its maximal causal power. This, of course, raises all sorts of interesting sociological and psychological questions about people who go unnoticed by society, but the reason Tononi makes this assertion is because it provides a means by which the theory can be measured—integrated information,


the details of which are beyond this blog post. Suffice it to say that the panel discussion at the conference was lively and interesting. But as FQXi’s fearless leader Max Tegmark pointed out, while IIT may or may not be correct, it is at least testable. As such, Christoph Koch of the Allen Brain Institute (who was at the 2014 conference but not at this year’s) has said it is “the only really promising fundamental theory of consciousness.”[1] That seems reason enough to study it.

[1] Carl Zimmer, "Sizing Up Consciousness by its Bits", New York Times, September 20, 2010.
32 comments | view comments


What Happens Inside the Wavefunction? Sean Carroll at the 5th FQXi Meeting
By ZEEYA MERALI • Aug. 21, 2016 @ 15:53 GMT

Sean Carroll
On Friday, cosmologist Sean Carroll spoke about his latest research into the emergence of space — and maybe gravity — from quantum entanglement.

Sophie Hebden has profiled Carroll’s work for us, in the article “In Search of a Quantum Spacetime.” Many physicists, when trying to think about what the world looks like on small scales, start with a classical framework — a picture of the world in which objects have definite properties — and then try to modify it to make it quantum. Carroll and his colleagues argue that nature is fundamentally quantum and work their way back to the world we see around us from that staring point.

Listen to the audio from his talk to find out more about this, and the idea of describing the evolution of systems in terms of “quantum circuits.”

Free Podcast

Sean Carroll asks What Happens Inside the Wavefunction? From the 5th FQXi International Meeting.

LISTEN:

Go to full podcast



More to follow soon...
9 comments | view comments


Dirty Secrets of…Quantum Foundations: Matt Leifer at the 5th FQXi Meeting
By ZEEYA MERALI • Aug. 20, 2016 @ 15:39 GMT

Matt Leifer
Audio from Matt Leifer’s talk from the FQXi meeting has now been posted here (video of this, and all other talks from the meeting will follow). If you’ve been following our essay contests over recent years, you’ll know that Leifer tends to place highly, and usually has something both profound and entertaining to say. His talk in the “Dirty Secrets” session lived up to expectations.

Leifer’s main target in his talk was the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, which he says most physicists subscribe to (though there were doubts expressed about that in the room). I’m wary of attempting to define what it is because a large part of Leifer’s argument is that there is no consistent definition. But it’s the interpretation attributed to a bunch of quantum theory’s founding fathers — and the one that physicists are often taught at school. It says that before you look, a quantum object is described by a wavefunction that encompasses a number of possibilities (a particle being here and there, a cat being dead and alive), and that when you look, this collapses into definiteness. Schrödinger’s equation allows you to calculate the probability of the outcome of a quantum experiment, but you can’t really know, and probably shouldn’t even worry about, what’s happening before you look.

Free Podcast

Quantum physicist Matt Leifer reveals the dirty secrets of quantum foundations: the Copenhagen Interpretation does not exist and Copenhagen-like interpretations are as crazy as invoking parallel universes. From the 5th International FQXi meeting.

LISTEN:

Go to full podcast



On top of that, Leifer argues that Copenhagen-like interpretations, rather than being the most sensible option (as is often claimed), are actually just as whacky as, for instance, the Many World’s Interpretation.

More to follow soon.
130 comments | view comments

Recent Blog Entries

Dirty Secrets of...Life: Paul Davies at the 5th...
By ZEEYA MERALI
[picture]Greetings from Banff, Alberta, where FQXi is currently holding its 5th international meeting.

The first session summarised the “dirty secrets of science”: cosmology, quantum foundations, quantum gravity, life, artificial...
August 19th, 2016 | 10 comments | view blog entry & comments

Announcing Physics of the Observer Grant Search...
By BRENDAN FOSTER
[picture]Last October, FQXi announced its new program on Physics of the Observer, including a request for proposals on research and outreach projects. We asked applicants to consider questions like, what does it mean to be an observer? What sort of...
August 5th, 2016 | 22 comments | view blog entry & comments

Happy 10th Birthday FQXi! Podcast: Space News,...
By ZEEYA MERALI
[picture]Believe it or not, it’s a decade since FQXi launched, back in May 2006. There’ll be more celebrations on the site to come, but to commemorate our birthday month, we invited one of FQXi’s directors, Anthony Aguirre, on to the latest...
May 31st, 2016 | 142 comments | view blog entry & comments

New Podcast: A MICROSCOPE on General Relativity,...
By ZEEYA MERALI
After a bit of a break, the FQXi podcast returns!

[picture]In the news round-up, Brendan Foster and I chat about the MICROSCOPE satellite experiment, which was launched in April to put the equivalence principle--and general relativity--to the...
May 2nd, 2016 | 100 comments | view blog entry & comments

David Ritz Finkelstein (1929 - 2016)
By BOB COECKE
We all just enjoyed the detection of gravitational waves due to two colliding black holes.  David Ritz Finkelstein, who passed away in January, was the first, in 1958, who identified Schwarzschild's solution of the GR equations as corresponding to a...
February 16th, 2016 | 6 comments | view blog entry & comments

LIGO to Make a Gravitational Waves Announcement on...
By ZEEYA MERALI
Updated 4:15pm Feb 11: Congratulations to the LIGO collaboration for successfully detecting gravitational waves from the merger of two black holes. Follow @FQXi on Twitter for live updates.

I’m opening this thread as a place to watch...
February 10th, 2016 | 184 comments | view blog entry & comments

RIP Edgar Mitchell
By WILLIAM OREM
Rest In Peace astronaut Edgar Mitchell, the sixth man to walk on the moon and the last member of the Apollo 14 mission. He was oddly credulous for a man of science, confusing the public with his proclamations that alien visitors interceded in the...
February 6th, 2016 | 1 comment | view blog entry & comments

How risky is too risky? Evaluating the expected...
By ANTHONY AGUIRRE
[picture]On Dec. 8, 2015, two different groups (sharing an author) posted papers to the arXiv announcing the possible detection of planet-sized objects in the far outer solar system (Vlemmings et al, arXiv:1512.02650v2 and Liseau et...
February 4th, 2016 | 81 comments | view blog entry & comments

Measuring Consciousness in the Lab
By MAX TEGMARK
[picture]If you're driving, you're having a subjective experience of colors, sounds and vibrations. But does a self-driving car have a subjective experience? Does it feel like anything at all to be a self-driving car, or is it a zombie in the sense...
January 14th, 2016 | 1044 comments | view blog entry & comments

2015 in Review: New Podcast on Planets, Particles...
By ZEEYA MERALI
We’re taking our annual look back at the physics highlights of the past 12 months — as chosen by FQXi member Ian Durham, a quantum physicist at Saint Anselm College in New Hampshire. Ian will be counting down his top 5 picks in a special podcast...
December 28th, 2015 | 199 comments | view blog entry & comments

Please enter your e-mail address:

And select the letter between 'Q' and 'S':


Note: Joining the FQXi mailing list does not give you a login account or constitute membership in the organization.